yimg
My starting point is the generation that inherited
Africa’s colonial legacy. Our generation followed on the heels of nationalists.
We went to school in the colonial period and to university after independence.
We were Africa’s first generation of postcolonial intellectuals. Our political
consciousness was shaped by a central assumption: we were convinced that the
impact of colonialism on our societies was mainly economic. In the decade that
followed African political independence, militant nationalist intellectuals
focused on the expropriation of the native as the great crime of colonialism. Walter
Rodney wrote How Europe Underdeveloped Africa.1 But no one wrote of how
Europe ruled Africa.
We were convinced that political economy was the most
appropriate tool to come to analytical grips with the colonial legacy. The
great contribution of underdevelopment theorists was to historicize the
construction of colonial markets and thereby of market-based identities. The
popularity of political economy spread like a forest fire in the
post-independence African academy precisely because it historicized colonial
realities, even if in a narrowly economic way. Political economy provided a way
of countering two kinds of colonial presumptions, embedded in various theories
of modernization.2 The first was that colonial cultures were not grounded in
historical processes. The second was that colonial contact marked the beginning
of a history for these societies, since colonialism was presumed to have
animated them culturally, economically, and politically.
The limits of political economy as a framework for
political analysis began to surface in the face of postcolonial political
violence, for political economy could only explain violence when it resulted
from a clash between market-based identities—either class or division of labor.
From this point of view, political violence had to be either revolutionary or
counterrevolutionary. In the face of political violence that cut across social
classes rather than between them—violence that was neither revolutionary nor
counterrevolutionary but simply nonrevolutionary, violence animated mainly by
distinctions crafted in colonial law rather than sprouting from the soil of a
commodity economy—explanations rooted in political economy offered less and
less analytical clarity. This limit provided an opening for a second coming of
cultural explanations of political conflict, most obviously those addressing
the political resurgence of ethnicity.
My objective here is to try to understand the spread of
nonrevolutionary political violence by breaking from widely held culturalist
assumptions in two ways. First, I will argue that the process of state
formation generates political identities that are distinct not only from
market- based identities but also from cultural identities. Second, faced with
a growing tendency to root causes of violence in cultural difference—now
ominously called a clash of civilizations 3 —I will differentiate between
cultural and political identities.
To return to the time of Rodney, it strikes me that none
of us—neither nationalists nor Marxists—historicized the political legacy of
colonialism, of the colonial state as a legal/institutional complex that
reproduced particular political identities. The tendency was to discuss agency
in an institutional void, by focusing on how it was harnessed to the colonial
project; Marxists called the agents “compradors” and nationalists called them
“collaborators.” Both bemoaned “tribe” and “tribalism” as colonial concoctions,
while assuming “race” and “racism” to exist as something real, in a positivist
sense. It was said that ethnicity was cultural and race biological. Neither
Marxists nor nationalists tried to historicize race and ethnicity as political
identities undergirded and reproduced by colonial institutions—perhaps because
neither had yet managed sufficient analytical distance from that legacy.
Because our emphasis on agency was to the exclusion of institutions, we failed
to historicize agency, to understand the extent to which colonial institutions
did shape the agency of the colonized.
The question of institutions of rule has surfaced only
recently, in the face of a breakdown of political institutions and an eruption
of internal conflict. In the West, it has stimulated an entire genre of
literature, generally called the literature on state collapse.4 When I first
heard of the crisis of governance in postcolonial Africa being referred to as a
state collapse, I was a bit suspicious. I remembered the tradition from
Aristotle to Hegel that considered the capacity for state life as the peak of
human historical achievement. I also remembered the Hamitic hypothesis, which
took all evidence of state-building in Africa as the influence of Hamites,
considered as black but not Negro. And I remembered that the rationale for
colonialism was always the need for tutelage, given that Africans were said to
lack the capacity to build stable states and a durable law and order.
On second thought, however, I
realized that these Africanists do have a point. There is a state collapse. But
the point they have is too general. It is not just any state that is
collapsing; it is specifically what remains of the colonial state in Africa that
is collapsing. True, Africa’s political institutions are in crisis. But which
institutions are these? If we look at the crisis closely, we will recognize at
its heart the institutional legacy of colonial rule, particularly the political
institutions of colonial rule.
There is also a second response to the crisis. It goes
under the name of Pan-Africanism. This tendency even has an organization by
that name, called the Pan-African Congress, with headquarters in Kampala
patronized by the Yoweri Museveni government and, until recently, by the entire
phalanx of what used to be referred to as the “new generation” of Africa’s
leaders: those from Rwanda, Ethiopia, Eritrea, and Libya. The Pan-Africanists
believe that state crisis is a crisis of colonial boundaries, because these
boundaries were and are artificial—in the African case more so, since they were
drawn up with a pencil and a ruler on a map at a conference table in Berlin in
the 1880s. Well, what would be genuine boundaries? From this point of view the
answer would be that they would be “natural,” meaning they would not cut
through ethnic boundaries. In other words, the political map of Africa should
have followed its cultural map.
I find two problems with this kind of argument. All
boundaries are artificial; none are natural. War and conquest have always been
integral to state-building. This was particularly the case before the era of
the extraordinary mobility of finance capital, and certainly of the
globalization that followed the collapse of the Soviet bloc—a development that
gave finance capital a truly global reach. Before the era of mobile finance
capital, shifting power relations often translated into shifting boundaries,
with each new boundary being claimed more natural than the previous one. With
the growing power of finance capital, however, all boundaries became porous.
The real problem with this point of view is the
assumption that cultural and political boundaries should coincide, and that the
state should be a nation-state—that the natural boundaries of a state are those
of a common cultural community. Basil Davidson called this “the curse of
the nation state,” but he was never able to define the institutional nature of
that curse.5 After arguing—rightly, I think—that the curse led to the politics
of ethnic cleansing in the Balkans, he argued—wrongly, and illogically—that the
problem in Africa was that Europe ignored the ethnic map of Africa. Thereby,
Davidson thought, Europe ignored Africa’s real traditions in drawing
state boundaries. So he brought us right back to the question of colonial
boundaries.
I will argue differently from both these schools. The
solution does not lie in bringing back the Europeans to address “state
collapse,” or even in “recolonization” by presumably more benign Africans, as
Ali Mazrui once suggested.6 Nor does the solution lie in redrawing Africa’s
boundaries. For no matter how much we redraw boundaries, the political crisis
will remain incomprehensible until we address the
institutional—political—legacy of colonial rule.
THE COLONIAL STATE AND LEGALLY INSCRIBED IDENTITIES
There is a language particular to the modern state,
including its colonial version. That is the language of law. Legal distinctions
are different from all others in that they are enforced by the state, and then
are in turn reproduced by institutions that structure citizen participation
within the state.
The colonial state made a distinction in law between
“race” and “ethnicity.” This is the question I would like to begin with. What
is the difference in law between a race and an ethnicity? Is it the difference
between biology and culture, between biological race and cultural ethnicity?
Not really, if you take a closer look. In indirect-rule Africa, only natives
were said to belong to ethnic groups; nonnatives had no ethnicity. Nonnatives
were identified racially, not ethnically. There was in fact an entire racial
hierarchy, with Europeans—meaning whites—at the top, followed by “Coloureds,”
then Asians, then Arabs, and then Hamites (the Batutsi). Races were considered
a civilizing influence, even if in different degrees, while ethnicities were
considered to be in dire need of being civilized.
The colonial state divided the population into two:
races and ethnicities. Each lived in a different legal universe. Races were
governed through civil law. They were considered as members, actually or
potentially, of civil society. Civil society excluded ethnicities. If we
understand civil society not as an idealized prescription but as a historical
construct, we will recognize that the original sin of civil society under
colonialism was racism.
Ethnicities were governed through customary laws. While
civil law spoke the language of rights, customary law spoke the language of
tradition, of authenticity. These were different languages with different
effects, even opposite effects. The language of rights bounded law. It claimed
to set limits to power. For civic power was to be exercised within the rule of
law, and had to observe the sanctity of the domain of rights. The language of
custom, in contrast, did not circumscribe power, for custom was enforced.
The language of custom enabled power instead of checking it by drawing
boundaries around it. In such an arrangement, no rule of law was possible.
Let me return to my basic point. Colonial law made a
fundamental distinction between two types of persons: those indigenous and
those not indigenous; in a word, natives and nonnatives. My first observation—I
will have a second one later—is that rights belonged to nonnatives, not to
natives. Natives had to live according to custom. Nationalism was a struggle of
natives to be recognized as a transethnic identity, as a race, as “Africans,”
and thus—as a race—to gain admission to the world of rights, to civil society,
which was a short form for civilized society. Before going farther, I
would like to take a closer look at the two worlds: the world of the native and
the world of the settler (which we shall see was not always synonymous with
“nonnative”), the world of the ethnicities and the world of races, the world of
customary law and the world of civil law.
Customary Law
In the indirect-rule state, there was never a single
customary law for all natives. For customary law was not racially specific; it
was ethnically specific. It made a horizontal distinction, a distinction in
law, between different ethnic groups. This was not a cultural but a legal
distinction. The point is that each ethnic group had to have its own law.
If Europe had nations, Africa was said to have ethnicities, then called tribes.
If every “historical” nation in Europe had its own state, every tribe in Africa
had to have its own native authority to enter history. If every nation-state in
Europe promulgated its own civic law, every native authority in Africa had to
enforce its own customary law. So went the logic of indirect rule.
The colonial state was from this point of view an ethnic
federation, comprising so many Native Authorities, each defined ethnically.
Each Native Authority was like a local state under central supervision. If
decolonization meant getting rid of the colonial power from the central state,
what should decolonization have meant in the local state? I wrote a book about
this in 1996, called Citizen and Subject.7 Here, let me simply say that
to answer the question one would need to take a closer look at what colonialism
constructed as custom. I have three things in mind.
First, precolonial Africa did not
have a single customary authority, but several. Each of these defined custom in
its own domain. There were thus age groups, clans, women’s groups, chiefs,
religious groups, and so on. It is worth noting that only one of
these—chiefs—was sanctified as a native authority under indirect-rule
colonialism, and only its version of custom was declared “genuine.” The rest
were officially silenced. In sanctifying the authoritarian version of custom as
“genuine,” colonial power sought to construct native custom as unchanging and
singular.
Second, this single native authority was reorganized as
despotic. If we contrast the mode of organization of civil and customary authority
under colonial rule, the point will be clear. Civic authority was organized on
the basis of functional specificity and the principle of a balance of power.
Even if there were no elections, there was a clear distinction between the
executive, the legislative, the judicial, and the administrative moments of
power. In contrast, the native authority was organized on the basis of a fusion
of power.
I chaired a commission of inquiry on local government in
Uganda the year after President Museveni came to power. We spent two years in
different parts of the country. One thing stood out in all areas, no matter how
different they were in other aspects: the relationship between the chief and
the peasant. When the year began, the chief would enumerate the peasant’s
property and assess it for tax purposes. If the peasant was dissatisfied, he
appealed to the chief. After the chief made a ruling, he would return to
collect tax. If the peasant failed to pay the tax, the chief would arrest him,
then decide where to put him to work during his prison term. At the end of the
term, the chief would release him and require him to pay the unpaid portion of
the original tax, as well as a fine on top of it for having failed to pay it in
the first place. This same chief could also pass and enforce bylaws, provided
they did not contradict a national law. For example, the chief could decide
that every peasant must donate a chicken for purposes of “development.” So the
cycle of life went on. The chief combined in his hands executive, legislative,
judicial, and administrative powers. When he faced the peasant, his fingers
closed and the hand became a clenched fist.
When we returned to Kampala from our district tours, we
began to meet officials at the Ministry of Local Government. The single most
enduring impression I carried away with me was how different the Ministry of
Local Government was from every other ministry that I knew of. Every line
ministry—be it the ministry of education, finance, agriculture, industry, or
health—was functionally specific except for one, the Ministry of Local
Government. Its concerns included primary—but not secondary—education,
feeder—but not major—roads, primary—but not hospital—health, and so on. The
Ministry of Local Government was like a state within the state. I realized that
this was the ministry for peasants. It was the heart of the colonial state.
The third common thing about customary law was
the great emphasis on corporal punishment. You could almost say that the very
definition of a customary authority was an authority that had the customary
right to use force to coerce subjects to follow custom. I wonder to what extent
this may also apply to Sharia law in the colonial context. I think there is
great need to historicize Sharia law, for even if God’s law may not change
historically, its application by humans on earth is susceptible to change. I
think we need particularly to look at two aspects of Sharia law in the
postcolonial context: the fusion between the executive and the judiciary, to
the exclusion of judicial interpretation (ijtihad), and the growing
emphasis on Hudud, that is, corporal punishment.
Civic Law
While ethnicities were demarcated horizontally and were
said to represent a cultural diversity, races were differentiated vertically
and were said to reflect a civilizational hierarchy. Some races were said to be
more civilized than others, and therefore were said to have a claim to higher
rights. While each ethnicity was said to have its own customary law, races were
constituted within a single legal domain, that of civil law, except that civil
law was full of discriminations; there were citizens of different categories,
some real, others virtual.
My second observation is that the distinction
between races and ethnicities was not the same as the distinction between
colonizers and colonized. The hierarchy of races included both colonizers and
colonized. Similarly, the colonized divided into those indigenous and those
not; in other words, whereas all natives were colonized, not all nonnatives
were colonizers. The hierarchy of race included master races and subject races.
Who were the subject races of indirect-rule Africa? They were the Indians of
East, Central and Southern Africa, the Arabs of Zanzibar, the Batutsi of Rwanda
and Burundi, and the “Coloureds” of Southern Africa. The distinction between
subject races and subject ethnicities is worth grasping. While both were
colonized, the former were a fraction of the latter. Subject races were either
nonindigenous immigrants, like the Indians of East, Central and Southern
Africa, or they were constructed as nonindigenous by the colonial powers, such
as, for example, the Batutsi of Rwanda and Burundi. In contrast, subject
ethnicities were indigenous. Finally, subject races usually performed a
middleman function, in either the state or the market, and their position was
marked by petty privilege economically and preferential treatment legally.
The distinction between subject races and subject
ethnicities recalls another distinction drawn in a different context by Malcolm
X. This is the distinction between the “Field Negro” and the “House Negro,” the
former in the field and the latter in the mansion. This distinction too was
marked by petty privilege and preferential treatment and, as a consequence, had
its own ideological effects. As Malcolm X put it, when the master was sick, the
House Negro would mimic the master—“We sick”—and when the master was tired, “We
tired.”
Precisely because the legal category “nonnative”
included both master races and subject races, it is important to distinguish
“nonnative” as a legal identity from “settler” as a political identity. To my
knowledge, the law never spoke of settlers, only of nonnatives. “Settler” was
rather a political libel hurled by natives at master races, not subject races.
The notion of “settler” distinguished conquerors from immigrants. It was an
identity undergirded by a conquest state, a colonial state.8 In the course of
time, anticolonial nationalism would splinter into two distinct, even
contradictory tendencies. Radical nationalism would identify settlers with
conquerors, whereas conservative nationalism would identify them with all
immigrants. In this latter category would belong the 1959 Revolution in Rwanda
and the 1963 Revolution in Zanzibar.
My main concern in this article is the following: how
does this institutional inheritance, with its legally enforced distinctions
between races and ethnicities, civil law and customary law, rights and custom,
subject races and subject ethnicities, play out after colonialism?
Postcolonial Dilemmas
I will speak of three postcolonial dilemmas. The first
arises from the growing tendency for indigeneity to become the litmus test for
rights under the postcolonial state, as under the colonial state. The second
dilemma arises from the fact that we have built upon this foundation and turned
indigeneity into a test for justice, and thus for entitlement under the
postcolonial state. The third dilemma arises from the growing tendency to
identify a colonially constructed regime of customary law with Africa’s
authentic tradition.
Indigeneity and Rights
To understand why the link between indigeneity and
rights continued to be reproduced after colonialism, we need to focus on the
character of conservative—mainstream—nationalism . Mainstream nationalism
shared with its radical counterpart a common effort to de-racialize civic
rights. In contrast to militant nationalists who were determined to
de-ethnicize the customary sphere, however, mainstream nationalists pledged to
reproduce the customary as the authentic tradition of Africa. As a consequence,
mainstream nationalists reproduced the dual legacy of colonialism. This time
around, though, they hoped to privilege indigenous over nonindigenous citizens.
In addition to civil rights for all citizens, those indigenous were given a
bonus: customary rights.
In this context arose the question of defining who was
indigenous and who was not, at both the central and the local levels. Within
the country as a whole, one had to decide which ethnic groups were indigenous
and which ones were not, for only the former would have a right to a native
authority of their own. Locally, each native authority would have to
distinguish between those ethnically indigenous and those not, for only the
former would belong to the native authority ethnically and thus have the right
of custom.
Let us begin with the first type of indigenous person.
How do you tell who is indigenous to the country and who is not? Given a
history of migration, what is the dividing line between the indigenous and the
nonindigenous? In 1997, a colleague and I undertook a mission for the Council
for the Development of Social Research in Africa (CODESRIA) to Kivu Province in
Congo. The particular focus of the mission was the citizenship dilemma of the
Kinyarwanda-speaking population of Kivu. In North Kivu, there were two
Kinyarwanda-speaking groups: Banyarutshuru and Banyamasisi. The former were
considered indigenous, the latter were not. We wondered why. The answer was
disarmingly simple: unlike the Banyarutshuru, whose presence predated Belgian
colonization, the Banyamasisi had only moved to Congo in the colonial period,
as labor migrants.
It is worth noting that whereas the Mobutist state
wavered in its legal treatment of colonial migrants, in 1972 even going to the
point of passing a decree that recognized as citizens all those who had been
resident on Congolese soil since 1959, the democratic opposition to Mobutu
showed little inclination to repudiate the colonial legacy on this question.
Organized as the Congolese National Conference, a gathering of over four
hundred civil society organizations and nearly one hundred political groups,
the democratic opposition passed a law in 1991 defining a Congolese as anyone
with an ancestor then living in the territory demarcated by Belgians as the
colony of Congo. Let us ponder the meaning of this declaration. It means that the
independent state of Congo accepts the establishment of the colonial state of
Congo as its official date of birth, the date establishing the line of
demarcation between those to be considered indigenous to the land and those to
be considered immigrants. The Congo was not and is not an exception. If we look
at the definition of citizenship in most African states, we will realize that
the colonial state lives on, albeit with some reforms. My point is that in
privileging the indigenous over the nonindigenous, we turned the colonial world
upside down, but we did not change it. As a result, the native sat on the top
of the political world designed by the settler. Indigeneity remained the test
for rights.
The native-settler dialectic is also played out at the
micro level, the level of the native authority. Where neither customary law nor
customary authority are de-ethnicized, the customary realm is uncritically
reproduced as authentic tradition. The dilemma here is that while the
population on the ground is multiethnic, the authority, the law, and the
definition of rights are mono- or uni-ethnic. The consequence is to divide the
population ethnically, empowering those considered indigenous and disempowering
others considered nonindigenous.
The irony is that this dialectic inevitably leads to an
unraveling of the movement built up as nationalist in the colonial period, for
the nonindigenous in the postcolonial period are less and less racial, more and
more ethnic. The clashes about rights too are less and less racial, more and
more ethnic. Put differently, ethnic clashes are more and more about rights,
particularly the right to land and to a native authority that can empower those
identified with it as ethnically indigenous. For evidence, look at Kivu in
eastern Congo, the Rift Valley in Kenya, or contemporary Nigeria.
There was a time when a clash of this sort was a signal
for an exodus: those branded nonindigenous would leave, their belongings on
their head, and run in the direction of home. Now, the tendency is for them to
fight it out. Faced with a native authority that divides the resident
population into two, pitting the indigenous against the nonindigenous, the
trend is for the nonindigenous to arm themselves in self-defense. Thus the
proliferation of armed militia in the context of ethnically driven clashes
around land and other rights.
At this point I suggest we pause and ask ourselves two
questions. First, is not the shift from a homeward flight to a tendency to
fight it out where one is resident proof enough that the definition of home has
changed? That immigrants of yesterday have now become indigenous? That were it
not for the form of the state and its definition of indigeneity, yesterday’s
immigrants would be today’s citizens? Second, what is likely to be our future
if these tendencies continue? For if they do, clashes will increase, not
decrease. The dilemma is the following: the commodity economy moves people at
the top and the bottom, traders and capitalists of all types at the top,
land-poor peasants and jobless workers below. The more dynamic the economy, the
greater the movement across native authorities; and the more the movement, the
greater the number of nonindigenous residents inside each native authority.
Here, then, is the structural dilemma: the commodity economy dynamizes, but the
state penalizes those more dynamic by defining them as settlers. Even with the
colonial power gone, we keep on defining every citizen as either a native or a
settler!
Indigeneity and
Entitlements
The second postcolonial dilemma arises from the
very struggle to decolonize. How do you address the past without reproducing
it? Just as customary law made a distinction between indigenous and
nonindigenous ethnicities as a claim for group rights, civil law made a distinction
between indigenous and nonindigenous races when it came to entitlements. From
the time it faced militant nationalist opposition after World War II, the
colonial state defined “native” entitlements in response to the struggle for
justice.
The history of entitlements has gone through two phases.
In the first phase, entitlements were at the expense of subject races.
Africa’s worst internal violence in the postcolonial period has targeted those
defined as subject races under colonialism. This was true both of the Tutsi of
Rwanda in the “social revolution” of 1959 and of the Arabs of Zanzibar in the
Zanzibar Revolution of 1963. It was also true, though to a lesser extent, of
the Asians of Uganda in 1972. The difference between these two types of cases lies
in the following: Where the subject races made a bid for power, as in Zanzibar
in 1963 and in Rwanda in 1959–1963 and 1994, they were slaughtered. Where their
demand was seen to be for the protection of privilege and not a quest for
power, they met a response disenfranchising them, as in the case of the Ugandan
Asians, which went as far as including expulsion.
The response of the subject races has been diverse.
During the constitutional discussions in Uganda in the early 1990s, the Ugandan
Asians who had returned demanded that they be listed in the new constitution as
one of Uganda’s ethnic groups. Not surprisingly, this bid for indigeneity was
seen by many as at the minimum an attempt to get legal protection against any
future expropriation, and maximally to get access to land as an ethnic home.
Also not surprisingly, it was rejected. The returning Arabs of Zanzibar opted
for a different way to secure the same objective: they gave full support to
liberalization and privatization, and thereby to narrowing the scope of
citizenship-based action against them. The Boers of South Africa have taken
both the Ugandan Asian and the Zanzibar Arab routes: the mainly Afrikaner poor
have agitated for an ethnic homeland, complete with a customary home, and their
own native authority that can enforce its own customary law, while the rich
have pinned their hopes on liberalization and privatization as their salvation
from majority demands for justice. Certainly the most tragic and troubling
response comes from the Tutsi of Rwanda. Like the Israelis after the Holocaust,
the Rwandan Tutsi also seem to have reached a conclusion that is more of a
cul-de-sac: their conclusion is that there can be no survival without power,
that the only durable peace possible is an armed peace.
It is the second phase in the development of the culture
of entitlement as a form of justice that shows the real dilemma of turning
indigeneity into the basis for entitlement. In this phase, conservative African
regimes—the bearers of mainstream nationalism—have succeeded in redividing
yesterday’s natives into postcolonial settlers and postcolonial natives. The
dilemma of indigeneity as the legal basis for entitlement is perhaps best
illustrated by the Nigerian case. I am referring specifically to the ethnic
character of the Nigerian federation, as embodied in the constitutional
provision that key federal institutions—universities, civil service, and,
indeed, the army—must reflect the “federal character” of Nigeria. This means
that entrance to federal universities, to the civil service, and to the army is
quota driven. Where quotas are set for each state in the Nigerian federation,
only those indigenous to the state may qualify for a quota. This means that all
Nigerians resident outside their ancestral home are considered nonindigenous in
the state in which they reside. The effective elements of the Nigerian
federation are neither territorial units called states, nor ethnic groups, but
those ethnic groups that have their own states.
The ethnic character of the
Nigerian federation has an outcome that reinforces two tendencies. First, given
the way “federal character” is defined, every ethnic group in Nigeria is
compelled sooner or later to seek its own ethnic home, its own native
authority, its own state in the Nigerian federation. Second, with each new
state, the number of Nigerians defined as nonindigenous in all its states
continues to grow. The cumulative outcome is to intensify the contradiction
between economic and political processes. I return to my original formulation:
the more the economy dynamizes, the more the polity disenfranchises. The irony
and the tragedy are that our postindependence political arrangement
disenfranchises those most energized by the commodity economy. Once the law
makes cultural identity the basis for political identity, it inevitably turns
ethnicity into a political identity.
The law thus penalizes those who try to fashion a future
different from the past by mechanically translating cultural into political
identities. We need to recognize that the past and the future overlap, as do
culture and politics, but they are not the same thing. Cultural communities
rooted in a common past do not necessarily have a common future. Some may have
a diasporic future. Similarly, political communities may include immigrants, and
thus be characterized by cultural diversities, even if there is a dominant
culture signifying a history shared by the majority. The point is that
political communities are defined, in the final analysis, not by a common past
but by a resolve to forge a common future under a single political roof,
regardless of how different or similar their pasts may be.
Our challenge is to define political identities as
distinct from cultural identities, without denying that there may be a
significant overlap between the two. One way of doing so is to accent common
residence over common descent—indigeneity—as the basis of rights. For
initiatives that tried to make this shift, we would need to turn to the second,
and militant, variant of nationalism. It is militant nationalism that tried to
deethnicize the colonial political legacy and thereby repudiate the notion that
indigeneity should be the basis of rights. Militant nationalist initiatives
were taken from both the seat of power and from oppositional standpoints. The key
experiences, in my view, were those of Tanzania under the leadership of Julius
Nyerere and the National Resistance Movement during its guerilla struggle in
Uganda from 1981 to 1986.
Our final challenge is also to rethink our notion of
custom, for the idea of “custom” is closely tied to the idea of “native.”
Rethinking the
Customary Regime
Custom is not just the authoritarian version rescued and
built upon by colonial power. It also includes emancipatory legacies officially
silenced by the same power. Neither custom nor sources of custom are singular.
Both are plural, multiple, and diverse. If custom is to have any meaning, its
reproduction has to be more through consent than through coercion. My point is
that every living tradition grows; it has both a past and a future. Consensus
can only be born of conflict. The idea of custom as some kind of geological
fossil from the past, one that cannot be questioned or changed, is one point of
view. This point of view has been key to identifying, buttressing, and
salvaging a domestic authoritarianism as an authentic tradition.
Colonially crafted customary authority had two big
African homes in the colonial period. One was Nigeria; the other was South
Africa. While the apartheid struggle tended to debunk customary authority as
antidemocratic, the postapartheid transition has kept custom intact, as
“customary” homes, “customary” authorities, and “customary” rights. Having at
first dismissed this legacy as “antidemocratic,” the African National Congress
has turned to embracing the regime of the customary as “tradition.” As a
result, postapartheid South Africa has a dual legal structure—as did apartheid
South Africa. While the new government has deracialized civil law, civil
society, and civil rights, it still works with an ethnicized “customary” law
enforced by an ethnicized native authority. If the legal definition of
nonnatives was as citizens governed under civic law and of natives as
tribespersons governed under customary law, would it be an exaggeration to say
that the postapartheid transition has given us a nonracial apartheid?
POLITICAL IDENTITY: A METHODOLOGICAL
CONSIDERATION
We are used to thinking of identities as either
market-based or cultural. Left-wing intellectuals generally saw “real”
identities as market-based class identities, such as “worker” and “capitalist,”
or “landlord” and “tenant.” Those on the right had a habit of arguing that the
“real” identity was cultural. Both agreed that political identities were to be
understood as expressions of prepolitical identities—“real” identities—in the
political arena. The left had its verifying literature on class struggle and
revolution, and the right had its version on tribalism and nationalism. Since
the end of the Cold War, there has been a growing tendency in the left also to
see political identities as expressions of cultural identities. The literature
on class struggle is gradually giving way to that on social movements. Thus it
is no longer only the right intelligentsia but also many on the left who now
call for rights, even self-determination, for ethnicities.
I want to suggest the need to think of political
identities as distinct from economic or cultural identities. If economic
identities are a consequence of the history of development of markets, and
cultural identities of the development of communities that share a common
language and meanings, political identities need to be understood as specifically
a consequence of the history of state formation. With the modern state,
political identities are inscribed in law. In the first instance, they are
legally enforced.
If the law recognizes you as member of an ethnicity, and
state institutions treat you as member of that particular ethnicity, then you
become an ethnic being legally. By contrast, if the law recognizes you as a
member of a racial group, then your legal identity is racial. You understand
your relationship to the state, and your relationship to other legally defined
groups through the mediation of the law and of the state, as a consequence of
your legally inscribed identity. Similarly, you understand your inclusion or
exclusion from rights or entitlements based on your legally defined and
inscribed race or ethnicity. From this point of view, both race and ethnicity
need to be understood as political—not cultural, or even biological—identities.
The tendency of the left has been to think of the law as
individuating or disaggregating classes and thus creating false identities. But
the law does not just individuate, it also collates. It does not just treat
each person as an abstract being—the owner of a commodity in the market, a
potential party to a contract—it also creates group identities. These
identities are legally inscribed and legally enforced. They shape our
relationship to the state and to one another through the state. In so doing,
they also form the starting point of our struggles.
DEMOCRACY AND INSTITUTIONS:
A CONCLUSION
Democracy is not just about who governs and how they are
chosen. More important, it is about how they govern, the institutions through
which they govern, and the institutional identities by and through which they
organize different categories of citizens. Colonialism was not just about the
identity of governors, that they were white or European; it was even more so
about the institutions they created to enable a minority to rule over a
majority. During indirect rule, these institutions unified the minority as
rights-bearing citizens and fragmented the majority as so many custom-driven
ethnicities. I have suggested that this is what the legal discourse on race and
ethnicity was all about. Instead of racializing the colonized into a majority
identity called “natives,” as did nineteenth-century direct rule,
twentieth-century indirect rule dismantled this racialized majority into so
many ethnicized minorities. Thus it was said that there were no majorities,
only minorities, in the African colonies.
This core colonial legacy is at the root of our dilemma,
the one I defined in the context of my discussion of the Nigerian federation.
That dilemma is the form of the state: the economy dynamizes, and the state
disenfranchises the most dynamic. In this context, what are we to do? How do we
support those disenfranchised? By demanding that each ethnicity also have its
own state or native authority, as, for example, in the new Ethiopian
constitution? If so, do we not risk multiplying the problem, since the number
of minorities will grow as do the number of ethnically defined states or native
authorities? To oppose that demand, however, would be seen to be joining forces
with ethnic chauvinists. Is there a way out of this dilemma? The only way out,
I have argued, is to rethink the institutional legacy of colonialism, and thus
to challenge the idea that we must define political identity, political rights,
and political justice first and foremost in relation to indigeneity. Let us
reconsider the colonial legacy that each of us is either a native or a settler.
It is with that compass in hand that we must fashion our political world.
In sum, I suggest we go beyond the conventional thought
that the real crime of colonialism was to expropriate the indigenous, and
consider that colonialism perpetrated an even greater crime. That greater crime
was to politicize indigeneity, first as a settler libel against the native, and
then as a native self-assertion.
Endnotes
1.
Walter Rodney, How Europe Underdeveloped Africa (Dar-es-Salaam: TPH,
1971).
2.
Immanuel Wallerstein, “The Uses of Racism,” London Review of Books 22,10
(18 May 2000):11–14.
3. See,
e.g., Samuel Huntington, The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of
World Order (New York: Simon and Schuster, 1996).
4. See,
William I. Zartman, Collapsed States: The Disintegration and Restoration of
Legitimate Authority (Boulder, Colo.: L. Rienner, 1995).
5.
Basil Davidson, The Black Man’s Burden: Africa and the Curse of the
Nation-State (New York: Times Books, 1992).
6. Ali
Mazrui, “Decaying Parts of Africa Need Benign Colonization,” International
Herald Tribune, 4 Aug. 1994; also see, CODESRIA Bulletin 2, (Dakar:
CODESRIA, 1994).
7.
Mahmood Mamdani, Citizen and Subject: Contemporary Africa and the Legacy of
Late Colonialism (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996).
8. See Mahmood Mamdani, “When Does
a Settler Become a Native? Reflections on the Colonial Roots of Citizenship in
Equatorial and South Africa.” Inaugural Lecture, University of Cape Town, New
Series no. 208, 13 May 1998.
Apply for Canadian immigration and citizenship
ReplyDeleteWebsite: http://www.immigrationmatters.info
Gunness & Associates has been providing Canadian immigration and citizenship services for more than 26 years. We have helped thousands of clients from all parts of the globe obtain their visas to come to Canada
Our Contact Information:
Gunness & Associates | Canadian immigration specialist
Phone: (416) 604-2669
Website: http://www.immigrationmatters.info
Email: info@immigrationmatters.info
yurtdışı kargo
ReplyDeleteresimli magnet
instagram takipçi satın al
yurtdışı kargo
sms onay
dijital kartvizit
dijital kartvizit
https://nobetci-eczane.org/
1YL
Almanya yurtdışı kargo
ReplyDeleteBelçika yurtdışı kargo
Bulgaristan yurtdışı kargo
Çekya yurtdışı kargo
Danimarka yurtdışı kargo
FF3ML
Antalya
ReplyDeleteÇorum
Uşak
Kayseri
Van
YWO1
yozgat
ReplyDeletesivas
bayburt
van
uşak
AKSQXM
bitlis
ReplyDeletesakarya
van
tunceli
ankara
CWRB
https://titandijital.com.tr/
ReplyDeleteşırnak parça eşya taşıma
karabük parça eşya taşıma
yozgat parça eşya taşıma
samsun parça eşya taşıma
5FWF
hatay evden eve nakliyat
ReplyDeleteısparta evden eve nakliyat
erzincan evden eve nakliyat
muğla evden eve nakliyat
karaman evden eve nakliyat
TOCP
muş evden eve nakliyat
ReplyDeleteçanakkale evden eve nakliyat
uşak evden eve nakliyat
ardahan evden eve nakliyat
eskişehir evden eve nakliyat
RFDZC
624A7
ReplyDeleteMersin Evden Eve Nakliyat
Iğdır Evden Eve Nakliyat
Mardin Lojistik
Edirne Lojistik
Karabük Evden Eve Nakliyat
0ACF3
ReplyDeleteBurdur Evden Eve Nakliyat
Van Evden Eve Nakliyat
Ağrı Parça Eşya Taşıma
Kayseri Parça Eşya Taşıma
Kırıkkale Evden Eve Nakliyat
51800
ReplyDeleteIsparta Parça Eşya Taşıma
Sivas Parça Eşya Taşıma
Bartın Parça Eşya Taşıma
Aydın Parça Eşya Taşıma
Muş Parça Eşya Taşıma
2701E
ReplyDeleteİstanbul Parça Eşya Taşıma
Kırşehir Lojistik
Eskişehir Parça Eşya Taşıma
Bursa Parça Eşya Taşıma
Iğdır Parça Eşya Taşıma
1D702
ReplyDeleteÇerkezköy Oto Boya
Ağrı Lojistik
Kilis Şehir İçi Nakliyat
Bursa Şehirler Arası Nakliyat
Edirne Parça Eşya Taşıma
Nevşehir Evden Eve Nakliyat
Kripto Para Borsaları
Çerkezköy Yol Yardım
Denizli Lojistik
081D5
ReplyDeletewinstrol stanozolol for sale
order testosterone propionat
pharmacy steroids
order steroids
order halotestin
steroid cycles
halotestin for sale
buy dianabol methandienone
order sarms
DEF34
ReplyDeleteÇerkezköy Sineklik
Isparta Parça Eşya Taşıma
Kars Lojistik
Erzincan Evden Eve Nakliyat
Mamak Fayans Ustası
Çerkezköy Ekspertiz
Çerkezköy Organizasyon
Omlira Coin Hangi Borsada
Gümüşhane Şehirler Arası Nakliyat
F81C5
ReplyDeleteErzurum Evden Eve Nakliyat
Isparta Evden Eve Nakliyat
AAX Güvenilir mi
Edirne Lojistik
Sincan Boya Ustası
Trabzon Şehir İçi Nakliyat
Bolu Şehirler Arası Nakliyat
Siirt Evden Eve Nakliyat
hacklink
0A75C
ReplyDeleteTunceli Evden Eve Nakliyat
Yenimahalle Parke Ustası
Sincan Boya Ustası
Keçiören Fayans Ustası
Şırnak Evden Eve Nakliyat
Tekirdağ Parke Ustası
Nevşehir Evden Eve Nakliyat
Bitexen Güvenilir mi
Yalova Evden Eve Nakliyat
08937
ReplyDeleteLikee App Beğeni Satın Al
Binance Ne Zaman Kuruldu
Sohbet
Binance Referans Kodu
Binance Sahibi Kim
Binance Borsası Güvenilir mi
Tesla Coin Hangi Borsada
Threads Beğeni Hilesi
Parasız Görüntülü Sohbet
hbtfthdrf
ReplyDeleteشركة تسليك مجاري بالاحساء